Indexicals, Context, and Implicit Content

Philosophy of Language » Lecture 8

Indexicals and Context

A problem for compositionality?

The many-but-only-one meanings of I

Context-sensitivity

Context

The Semantics of Indexicals: Context and Circumstance

First Attempt to Connect Context and Truth

Making and Reporting Context-Sensitive Utterances

Triviality and Embedding

Necessity and Triviality

What’s gone wrong?

Double Indexing (Speaks 2024: §2.1.4)

Two Kinds of Meaning: Content and Character

Content and Character

The content of an expression is always taken with respect to a given context of use. Thus when I say ‘I was insulted yesterday’ a specific content – what I said – is expressed. Your utterance of the same sentence, or mine on another day, would not express the same content. … This content … has been often referred to as a ‘proposition’. So my theory is that different contexts … produce not just different truth values, but different propositions.

… I call that component of the sense of an expression which determines how the content is determined by the context, the ‘character’…. Just as content … can be represented by functions from possible worlds to extensions, so characters can be represented by functions from contexts to contents. The character of I would then be represented by the function … which assigns to each context the content which is represented by the constant function from possible worlds to the agent of the context. (Kaplan 1979: 83–84)

Illustrating the Standard Picture

Figure 1: The Relationship of Character, Context, Content, and Circumstance (Speaks 2024: §2.1.4).

The standard picture

Context-Sensitivity and Rigidity

Table 1: Combinations of rigidity and context-sensitivity.
Rigid Non-Rigid
Context-Sensitive Indexicals: I, here The man next to me now
Invariant Names: Antony, Gödel The man next to Antony on April 7, 1993

Analyticity

What is it that a competent speaker of English knows about the word ‘I’? … It is the character of ‘I’ …. Thus that component of sense which I call ‘character’ is best identified with what might naturally be called ‘meaning’.…

(c)
In all contexts, an utterance of [‘I am here’] expresses a true proposition [i.e., when evaluated at the context itself].

On the basis of (c), we might claim that [‘I am here’] is analytic (i.e., it is true solely in virtue of its meaning). Although [‘I am here’] rarely or never expresses a necessary proposition. This separation of analyticity from necessity is made possible – even, I hope, plausible — by distinguishing the kinds of entities of which ‘is analytic’ and ‘is necessary’ are properly predicated: characters (meanings) are analytic, contents (propositions) are necessary. (Kaplan 1979: 84–85)

A priority and Necessity: Stalnaker’s proposal

Worlds, Propositions and Circumstances

Where is Context-Sensitivity to be Found?

Tests for Context-Sensitivity

Unreliability of IDR test: On the left (Hawthorne 2006)

Terms for relative directions, like ‘left’, seem to be almost as obviously context-sensitive as ‘I’; the direction picked out by simple uses of ‘left’ depends on the orientation of the speaker of the context. But we can typically use ‘left’ in disquotational ‘says’ reports of the relevant sort. Suppose, for example, that Mary says

The coffee machine is to the left.

Sam can later truly report Mary’s speech by saying

Mary said that the coffee machine was to the left.

despite the fact that Sam’s orientation in the context of the ascription differs from Mary’s orientation in the context of the reported utterance. Hence our test seems to lead to the absurd result that ‘left’ is not context-sensitive. (Speaks 2024: §2.3.1)

Another test: Agreement

If \(A\) and \(B\) both utter \(S\) and can be reported as agreeing, say, with ‘\(A\) and \(B\) agree that \(S\)’, then that is evidence \(S\) is semantically invariant across its distinct utterances. If, on the contrary, distinct utterances cannot be so reported, this is evidence \(S\) is not semantically invariant across its distinct context of utterance. (Cappelen and Hawthorne 2009: 54–55)

Some more possible examples

Table 2: Verdicts of tests for context-sensitivity; ‘+’ means ‘is judged context-sensitive by the test’
Expression IDR Agreement A2
actually + + +
flat ?/+ ? +
tasty ? - ?/+

Is Knows an Indexical?

Pronouns

Pronouns and Context-Sensitivity

Pronouns and Binding

Donkey Anaphora

  1. Each man who owns a donkey beats it.

Here, again, in the most natural reading, it cannot be referential. A speaker of this sentence would not be referring to some particular donkey, Flossy, and saying that every man who owns a donkey beats Flossy. There is no consensus, however, on what the pronoun here does mean. (Elbourne 2011: 116)

Compositionality and Donkey Anaphora

E-type pronouns

  1. Amy owns a donkey. She cares for it.

Implicit Content and Unarticulated Constituents

Context and Content Again

  1. It’s raining.

Supplanting the Contextual Location

Unarticulated constituents

In order to assign a truth-value to [It’s raining], as I just did, I needed a place. But no component of [this] statement stood for a place. The verb ‘raining’ supplied the relation rains\((t,p)\) – a dyadic relation between times and places, as we have just noted. The tensed auxiliary ‘is’ supplies a time, the time at which the statement was made. ‘It’ doesn’t supply anything, but is just syntactic filler. ([Perry’s footnote:] Note that if we took ‘It’ to be something like an indexical that stood for the location of the speaker, we would expect ‘It is raining here’ to be redundant and ‘It is raining in Cincinnati but not here’ to be inconsistent.) So Palo Alto is a constituent of the content of my son’s remark, which no component of his statement designated; it is an unarticulated constituent. Where did it come from? (Perry 1986: 138)

  1. Everyone is smoking.

Three Approaches to Unarticulated Constituents

Approach 1: Propositional Radicals

How to Fill a Gappy Proposition

A Global Solution?

Gaps Filled New Ways

Approach 2: Covert Variables (Stanley 2005)

Stanley and Szabó on Covert Indexicals

A sentence [like every bottle is on the shelf] can communicate a proposition concerning a restricted domain of bottles, because, relative to certain contexts, it expresses such a proposition. It expresses such a proposition relative to certain contexts because common nouns such as ‘bottle’ always occur with a domain index. It follows that, in the logical form of quantified sentences, there are variables whose values, relative to a context, are (often restricted) quantifier domains. (Stanley and Szabó 2000: 258)

Applying covert variables to It’s raining I

(An omitted syntactic tree.)

Applying covert variables to It’s raining II

(Another omitted syntactic tree.)

The Binding Argument

Approach 3: Pragmatic Enrichment

References

Bach, Kent (1994) ‘Conversational Impliciture’, Mind & Language 9: 124–62. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.1994.tb00220.x.
Cappelen, Herman and John Hawthorne (2009) Relativism and Monadic Truth. Oxford University Press.
DeRose, Keith (1995) ‘Solving the Skeptical Problem’, Philosophical Review 104: 1–52. doi:10.2307/2186011.
Descartes, René (1641/1996) Meditations on First Philosophy: With Selections from the Objections and Replies, John Cottingham, ed., trans. Cambridge University Press.
Donaldson, Tom and Ernie Lepore (2012) ‘Context-Sensitivity’, in Gillian Russell and Delia Graff Fara, eds., The Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Language: 116–31. Routledge.
Elbourne, Paul (2005) Situations and Individuals. MIT Press.
Elbourne, Paul (2011) Meaning: A Slim Guide to Semantics. Oxford University Press.
Evans, Gareth (1980) ‘Pronouns’, Linguistic Inquiry 11: 337–62.
Hawthorne, John (2006) ‘Causal Structuralism’, in Metaphysical Essays: 211–27. Oxford University Press.
Heim, Irene and Angelika Kratzer (1998) Semantics in Generative Grammar. Blackwell.
Kaplan, David (1979) ‘On the Logic of Demonstratives’, Journal of Philosophical Logic 8. doi:10.1007/bf00258420.
King, Jeffrey C and Karen S Lewis (2021) Anaphora, in Edward N Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/anaphora/.
Kripke, Saul (1980) Naming and Necessity. Harvard University Press.
Lasersohn, Peter (2005-12) ‘Context Dependence, Disagreement, and Predicates of Personal Taste*’, Linguistics and Philosophy 28: 643–86. doi:10.1007/s10988-005-0596-x.
Neale, Stephen (1993) Descriptions, A Bradford Book. MIT Press.
Perry, John (1986) ‘Thought Without Representation’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 60: 137–51. doi:10.1093/aristoteliansupp/60.1.137.
Portner, Paul H (2005) What Is Meaning? Fundamentals of Formal Semantics. Wiley-Blackwell.
Richard, Mark (1981) ‘Temporalism and Eternalism’, Philosophical Studies 39: 1–13. doi:10.1007/bf00354808.
Soames, Scott (1986) ‘Incomplete Definite Descriptions’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 27: 349–75. doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1093636680.
Speaks, Jeff (2024) Theories of Meaning, in Edward N Zalta and Uri Nodelman, eds., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2024/entries/meaning/.
Stalnaker, Robert C (1978/1998) ‘Assertion’, in Context and Content: 78–95. Oxford University Press.
Stanley, Jason (2004) ‘On the Linguistic Basis for Contextualism’, Philosophical Studies 119: 119–46. doi:10.1023/b:phil.0000029353.14987.34.
Stanley, Jason (2005) ‘Semantics in Context’, in Gerhard Preyer and Georg Peter, eds., Contextualism in Philosophy: 221–53. Oxford University Press.
Stanley, Jason and Zoltán Gendler Szabó (2000) ‘On Quantifier Domain Restriction’, Mind and Language 15: 219–61. doi:10.1111/1468-0017.00130.
Stanley, Jason and Timothy Williamson (1995) ‘Quantifiers and Context-Dependence’, Analysis 55: 291–95. doi:10.1093/analys/55.4.291.
Zimmerman, Dean W (2005) ‘The A-theory of Time, the B-theory of Time, and “Taking Tense Seriously”, Dialectica 59: 401–57. doi:10.1111/j.1746-8361.2005.01041.x.