Lexical Semantics – Synonymy, Ambiguity, Vagueness

Philosophy of Language » Lecture 3

Plan for this lecture

Synonymy and Twin Earth

Synonymy

Synonymy and Extension

The Twin Earth Scenario

Twin Earth is very much like Earth… One of the peculiarities of Twin Earth is that the liquid called ‘water’ is not H2O but a different liquid whose chemical formula is very long and complicated. I shall abbreviate this chemical formula simply as XYZ. I shall suppose that XYZ is indistinguishable from water at normal temperatures and pressures. Also, I shall suppose that the oceans and lakes and seas of Twin Earth contain XYZ and not water, that it rains XYZ on Twin Earth and not water, etc.

If a space ship from Earth ever visits Twin Earth, then the supposition at first will be that ‘water’ has the same meaning on Earth and on Twin Earth. This supposition will be corrected when it is discovered that ‘water’ on Twin Earth is XYZ, and the Earthian space ship will report somewhat as follows.

On Twin Earth the word ‘water’ means XYZ. (Putnam 1973: 700–701)

The extension of water

Non-Supervenience of Meaning on Psychology…

…is a Problem for Internalism

  1. If the meaning of water is the concept water, water on Earth and water on Twin Earth are synonyms.

  2. Since different things fall under water on Earth and water on Twin Earth, water on Earth and water on Twin Earth are not synonyms. (Conceptual Non-Synonymy)

  3. So the meaning of water is not the concept water. (1, 2, modus tollens)

Internalist Responses

  1. Deny (1). Perhaps the radical Chomskyian internalist who denies any words are synonyms can do this in a principled way. But it would be a cost to internalism if it couldn’t account for such a basic property as synonymy.
  2. Deny (2). Again, the Chomskyian who is indifferent to the external world except insofar as it manifests in differences that are detectable by our cognitive system may be indifferent to the difference between H2O and XYZ. But that puts the internalist squarely in the line of Frege’s objection that internalism makes words mean the wrong things.
  3. Accuse the argument of equivocation: the word synonym itself means different things – it means something like, ‘connected to the same concept’ in (1), but ‘having the same referent’ in (2).

Referentialism Revisited

The Role of Concepts for Referentialists

Wide Content

Ambiguity, Homonymy, and Polysemy

Ambiguity of Meaning

An Internalist Taxonomy

Homonymy

Figure 1: An ambiguous figure: the Duck-Rabbit.

Polysemy

Ambiguity, Words, and Internalism

Against Polysemy

My theory is that there is no such thing as polysemy. The appearance that there is a problem is generated by the assumption that there are definitions; if you take the assumption away, the problem disappears. … definitions don’t solve the problem of polysemy; definitions are the problem of polysemy.

People sometimes say ‘exist’ must be ambiguous because look at the difference between ‘chairs exist’ and ‘numbers exist’. A familiar reply goes: the difference between the existence of chairs and the existence of numbers seems, on reflection, strikingly like the difference between numbers and chairs. Since you have the latter to explain the former, you don’t also need ‘exist’ to be polysemic. (Fodor 1998: 53–54)

Vagueness

Vagueness, Imprecision, and Generality

Figure 2: The yellow-orange-red colour spectrum with wavelengths

Borderlines and Margins

A vague word admits of borderline cases, cases in which we don’t know whether to apply the word or not, even though we have all the kinds of information which we would normally regard as sufficient to settle the matter. We may see how tall a man is, or even know his height to a millimetre, yet be unable to decide whether he counts as tall or not. We may see a collection of grains of sand, and even know exactly how many grains of sand the collection contains, yet not know whether it should be called a heap or not. … This ignorance is not a manifestation of any failure to understand our language. (Sainsbury 2009: 41)

If \(a\) and \(b\) are very close in \(F\)-relevant respects, then ‘\(Fa\)’ and ‘\(Fb\)’ are very close in respect of truth. (Smith 2005: 164)

since colours form a continuum … there are shades of colour concerning which we shall be in doubt whether to call them red or not, not because we are ignorant of the meaning of the word ‘red’, but because it is a word the extent of whose application is essentially doubtful. (Russell 1923: 85)

Vagueness Puzzles: the Sorites

One puzzle posed by vagueness is the traditional sorites, or the paradox of the heap.

  1. A 10,000-grained pile of sand is lots of sand.

  2. If a \(n\)-grained pile of sand is lots, then so is an \(n-1\)-grained pile. (No sharp cutoffs for vague predicates like lots; the so-called Tolerance principle)

  3. A 9,999-grained pile is lots. (From 10, 11, logic)

  4. A 9,998-grained pile is lots. (From 12, 11, logic)

\[\vdots\]

  1. A 1-grained pile is lots. (Follow the preceding pattern)

We could run the same format for red, bald, etc.: any vague word linked to an underlying smoothly varying quantity (wavelength, number of hairs, …).

Options

Options in resolving the sorites.
Option View
Reject premise Epistemicism (Williamson 1994); Supervaluationism (Fine 1975); Degree theory (Smith 2008)
Reject reasoning Degree theory (Edgington 1996)
Accept conclusion Eliminativism (Unger 1979)

Vagueness puzzles: ontology and semantics

Vagueness and Referentialism

Deploying Classical Semantic Values: Epistemicism

Deploying Classical Semantic Values: Supervaluationism

Vagueness and Internalism

Concepts and the Sorites

Vagueness and Internalism

References

Burge, Tyler (1993) ‘Concepts, Definitions, and Meaning’, Metaphilosophy 24: 309–25. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9973.1993.tb00198.x.
Edgington, Dorothy (1996) ‘Vagueness by Degrees’, in Rosanna Keefe and Peter Smith, eds., Vagueness: A Reader: 294–316.
Égré, Paul, David Ripley, and Steven Verheyen (2019) ‘The Sorites Paradox in Psychology’, in Sergi Oms and Elia Zardini, eds., The Sorites Paradox: 263–86. Cambridge University Press.
Elbourne, Paul (2011) Meaning: A Slim Guide to Semantics. Oxford University Press.
Fine, Kit (1975) ‘Vagueness, Truth and Logic’, Synthese 30: 265–300. doi:10.1007/bf00485047.
Fodor, Jerry A (1998) Concepts. Oxford University Press.
Kaplan, David (1990) Words, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 64: 93–119.
Kripke, Saul A (1977) ‘Speaker’s Reference and Semantic Reference’, Midwest Studies In Philosophy 2: 255–76. doi:10.1111/j.1475-4975.1977.tb00045.x.
Putnam, Hilary (1973) ‘Meaning and Reference’, The Journal of Philosophy 70: 699–711. doi:10.2307/2025079.
Russell, Bertrand (1923) ‘Vagueness’, The Australasian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy 1: 84–92. doi:10.1080/00048402308540623.
Sainsbury, Richard Mark (2009) Paradoxes, 3rd edition. Cambridge University Press.
Smith, N J J (2008) Vagueness and Degrees of Truth. Oxford University Press.
Smith, Nicholas JJ (2005) ‘Vagueness as Closeness’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 83: 157–83. doi:10.1080/00048400500110826.
Taylor, John R (2015) Prototype Theory in Linguistics, in James D Wright, ed., International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, vol. 19, 2nd edition: 286–89. Elsevier.
Unger, Peter (1979) ‘There Are No Ordinary Things’, Synthese 41: 117–54. doi:10.1007/bf00869568.
Wikforss, Åsa (2007) ‘Semantic Externalism and Psychological Externalism’, Philosophy Compass 3: 158–81. doi:10.1111/j.1747-9991.2007.00107.x.
Williams, J R G (2012) ‘Vagueness’, in Gillian Russell and Delia Graff Fara, eds., Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Language: 143–52. Routledge. http://www.personal.leeds.ac.uk/~phljrgw/wip/FinalVagueness.pdf.
Williamson, Timothy (1994) Vagueness. Routledge.