Omniscience and Freedom

God, Faith and Infinity » Lecture 7

Omniscience

Defining Omniscience

Boethius on God, Eternity, Atemporality

All who live by reason agree that God is eternal, and we must therefore think about what eternity means. This will clarify what the divine nature is and also what divine knowledge must be. Eternity is the whole, simultaneous, perfect possession of limitless life… it has knowledge of the whole of life, can see the future, and has lost nothing of the past. It is in an eternal present and has an understanding of the entire flow of time. …

It is one thing to proceed through infinite time, as Plato posits, but quite another to embrace the whole of time in one simultaneous present. This is obviously a property of the mind of God. …

The endless and infinite changing of things in time is an attempt to imitate eternity, but it cannot equal its immobility and it fails to achieve the eternal present, producing only an infinite number of future and past moments. … if we use proper terms, then … we should say that God is eternal but the world is perpetual. (Boethius 524 CE: 168–70).

Divine Omniscience

Is God a Knower?

Evidentialist Conceptions of Knowing

Freedom and Foreknowledge

Another View of Permanent Presence

Free Action

Is this a Genuine Issue?

Pike’s argument (1965: 33–34)

(P1)
God is omniscient at \(t_{1}\).
(P2)
If Jones does X at \(t_{2}\) (later than \(t_{1}\)), then God knows at \(t_{1}\) that Jones does X at \(t_{2}\). (From P1)
(P3)
If God knows at \(t_{1}\) that Jones does X at \(t_{2}\) and Jones has the power to refrain from doing X at \(t_{2}\), then ‘it was within Jones’s power at \(t_{2}\) to do something that would have brought it about that’ either:
  1. ‘God held a false belief at \(t_{1}\)’; or
  2. ‘God did not hold the belief He held at \(t_{1}\)’; or
  3. ‘God … did not exist at \(t_{1}\)’.
(P4)
No one has the power to do something that would bring about any of the things mentioned under (P3).
(P5)
So if Jones does X at \(t_{2}\), Jones cannot refrain from doing X at \(t_{2}\). (P2–P4)
(P6)
So Jones’ doing X at \(t_{2}\) would not be free or voluntary. (from P5)

Defending (P3)

(P4) expanded

  1. It is not within one’s power at a given time to do something having a description that is logically contradictory.
  2. It is not within one’s power at a given time to do something that would bring it about that someone who held a certain belief at a time prior to the time in question did not hold that belief at the time prior to the time in question.
  3. It is not within one’s power at a given time to do something that would bring it about that a person who existed at an earlier time did not exist at that earlier time. (Pike 1965: 33–34)

Changing the Past – Time Travel Scenarios

But the events of a past moment are not subdivisible into temporal parts and therefore cannot change. Either the events of 1921 timelessly do include Tim’s killing of Grandfather, or else they timelessly don’t. We may be tempted to speak of the “original” 1921 that lies in Tim’s personal past, many years before his birth, in which Grandfather lived; and of the “new” 1921 in which Tim now finds himself waiting in ambush to kill Grandfather. But if we do speak so, we merely confer two names on one thing. The events of 1921 are doubly located in Tim’s (extended) personal time, like the trestle on the railway, but the “original” 1921 and the “new” 1921 are one and the same. If Tim did not kill Grandfather in the “original” 1921, then if he does kill Grandfather in the “new” 1921, he must both kill and not kill Grandfather in 1921 – in the one and only 1921, which is both the “new” and the “original” 1921. It is logically impossible that Tim should change the past by killing Grandfather in 1921. So Tim cannot kill Grandfather. (Lewis 1976: 150)

Knowledge from Future Testimony

God’s Knowledge of the Uncertain Future

Laws and Knowledge

Revisiting (P4)

Denying the inference from (P5) to (P6)

Black … wishes to see White dead but is unwilling to do the deed himself. Knowing that Mary Jones also despises White … Black inserts a mechanism into Jones’s brain that enables Black to monitor and to control Jones’s neurological activity. If the activity in Jones’s brain suggests that she is on the verge of deciding not to kill White when the opportunity arises, Black’s mechanism will intervene and cause Jones to decide to commit the murder. On the other hand, if Jones decides to murder White on her own, the mechanism will not intervene. … Now suppose that when the occasion arises, Jones decides to kill White without any “help” from Black’s mechanism. … Jones is morally responsible for her act. Nonetheless, it appears that she is unable to do otherwise since if she had attempted to do so, she would have been thwarted by Black’s device. (Zagzebski 2017: §2.5)

Unknowable Truths

Self-Reference and Unknowability

Another Example: the Knower

Logic and Formalisation

The Knowledge Predicate

The proof rule of Factivity

The Ingredients of Self-Reference

Omniscience formalised

The proof rule of Omniscience

A proof

A proof that \mathbf{O} is false

A Residual Problem

A proof of \mathbf{\kappa}

Unknowable Truths Without Self-Reference

Fitch’s argument

  1. Assume \(p\) is an unknown truth, so that this conjunction is true: \((p \wedge ¬\mathop{\mathbf{K}} p)\).
  2. Assume that the unknowability of the unknown truth is knowable: \(\lozenge\mathop{\mathbf{K}}(p \wedge ¬\mathop{\mathbf{K}} p)\).
  3. In some world: \(\mathop{\mathbf{K}}(p \wedge ¬\mathop{\mathbf{K}} p)\). (possibly means ‘in some possible world’, 2)
  4. In some world: \((\mathop{\mathbf{K}} p \wedge \mathop{\mathbf{K}}¬\mathop{\mathbf{K}} p)\). (3, distribution)
  5. In some world: \((\mathop{\mathbf{K}} p \wedge ¬\mathop{\mathbf{K}} p)\). (4, factivity of right conjunct)
  6. \(\lozenge (\mathop{\mathbf{K}} p \wedge ¬\mathop{\mathbf{K}} p)\) (possible world to possibly, 5)
  7. \(¬\lozenge\mathop{\mathbf{K}}(p \wedge ¬\mathop{\mathbf{K}} p)\) (reductio, 2–6)
  8. If there is an unknown truth \(p\), there is an unknowable truth – namely, that \(p\) is an unknown truth. (conditional introduction, 1–7)

Is there an unknown truth?

Size Problems

Sets and Collections

Cantor’s Theorem

Cantor
The powerset \(\wp A\) of a set \(A\) is always bigger than \(A\).

The Set of All Truths?

Against God from Unknown Truth

Indexical Knowledge

The Essential Indexical

I once followed a trail of sugar on a supermarket floor… seeking the shopper with the torn sack to tell him he was making a mess. With each trip around the counter, the trail became thicker. But I seemed unable to catch up. Finally it dawned on me. I was the shopper I was trying to catch.

I believed at the outset that the shopper with a torn sack was making a mess. And I was right. But I didn’t believe that I was making a mess. That seems to be something I came to believe. And when I came to believe that, I stopped following the trail around the counter…. My change in beliefs seems to explain my change in behavior.… At first characterizing the change seems easy. My beliefs changed, didn’t they, in that I came to have a new one, namely, that I am making a mess? But things are not so simple.

The reason they are not is the importance of the word ‘I’ in my expression of what I came to believe. When we replace it with other designations of me, we no longer have an explanation of my behavior…. It seems to be an essential indexical. (Perry 1979: 3)

Omniscience and the Essential Indexical

In order to qualify as omniscient or all-knowing, a being must know at least all that is known. Such a being must, then, know what I know in knowing (1):

(1)
I am making a mess.

But what I know in such a case, it appears, is known by no omniscient being. The indexical ‘I’, as argued above, is essential to what I know in knowing (1). But only I can use that ‘I’ to index me—no being distinct from me can do so. I am not omniscient. But there is something that I know that no being distinct from me can know. Neither I nor any being distinct from me, then, is omniscient: there is no omniscient being.

A being distinct from me could, of course, know (3):

(3)
Patrick Grim is making a mess.

But as argued above this does not amount to what I know in knowing (1). (Grim 1985: 154)

References

Boethius (524 CE/2008) The Consolations of Philosophy, David R Slavitt, trans. Harvard University Press.
Fitch, Frederic B (1963) ‘A Logical Analysis of Some Value Concepts’, Journal of Symbolic Logic 28: 135–42. doi:10.2307/2271594.
Frankfurt, Harry G (1969) Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility, Journal of Philosophy 66: 829–39.
Goldman, Alvin I (1967) ‘A Causal Theory of Knowing’, The Journal of Philosophy 64: 357–72. doi:10.2307/2024268.
Grim, Patrick (1985) ‘Against Omniscience: The Case from Essential Indexicals’, Noûs 19: 151–80. doi:10.2307/2214928.
Grim, Patrick (1988) ‘Logic and Limits of Knowledge and Truth’, Noûs 22: 341. doi:10.2307/2215708.
Grim, Patrick (2013) ‘Problems with Omniscience’, in J P Moreland, Chad Meister and Khaldoun A Sweis, eds., Debating Christian Theism: 169–80. Oxford University Press.
Kaplan, David and Richard Montague (1960) ‘A Paradox Regained’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 1: 79–90. doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1093956549.
Leftow, Brian (1991) ‘Timelessness and Foreknowledge’, Philosophical Studies 63: 309–25. doi:10.1007/bf00354196.
Lewis, David (1976) The Paradoxes of Time Travel, American Philosophical Quarterly 13: 145–52.
Lewis, David (1981) ‘Are We Free to Break the Laws?’, Theoria 47: 113–21. doi:10.1111/j.1755-2567.1981.tb00473.x.
Oppy, Graham and Michael Scott, eds. (2010) Reading Philosophy of Religion. Wiley-Blackwell.
Perry, John (1979) ‘The Problem of the Essential Indexical’, Noûs 13: 3–21. doi:10.2307/2214792.
Pike, Nelson (1965) ‘Divine Omniscience and Voluntary Action’, The Philosophical Review 74: 27–46. doi:10.2307/2183529.
Routley, Richard (2010) ‘Necessary Limits to Knowledge: Unknowable Truths’, Synthese 173: 107–22. doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9679-5.
Tymoczko, Thomas (1984) ‘An Unsolved Puzzle about Knowledge’, The Philosophical Quarterly 34: 437–58. doi:10.2307/2219063.
Zagzebski, Linda (2017) ‘Foreknowledge and Free Will’, in Edward N Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/free-will-foreknowledge/.