Philosophy of Language » Lecture 10
So far we have focussed mostly on declarative sentences: sentences that have truth conditions, and express propositions when uttered.
But, as Austin points out, to focus on the truth-expressing use of declarative sentences can be to miss the point.
Suppose you say, in the appropriate circumstances,
What you say has truth conditions: it is true if indeed you call upon them, etc., etc., and false otherwise.
But of course you do more than state a truth in uttering (1) – you get married! You do something by saying something.
…it would be absurd to regard the thing that I say as a report of the performance of the action which is undoubtedly done… we should rather say that, in saying what I do, I actually perform that action. When I say ‘I name this ship the Queen Elizabeth’ I do not describe the christening ceremony, I actually perform the christening; and when I say ‘I do’… I am not reporting on a marriage, I am indulging in it.
Now these kinds of utterance are the ones we call performative utterances. (Austin 1956: 235)
A performative – what Austin calls the illocutionary act associated with an utterance (Austin 1975: 98) – is one you can perform by saying that you are performing it, when in appropriate circumstances:
The above example sentences would, if uttered appropriately, constitute performative acts. They are also all performative sentences (Austin 1956: 241). But the connection is contingent:
[A] speech act is a type of act that can be performed by speaker meaning that one is doing so. (Green 2021: §2)
A speech act can misfire, if the circumstances aren’t right (Austin 1956: 238; Searle 1975: 349). I can’t appoint you to the bench, or knight you, or name you (though I have been able to name some people). If you are already married, you can’t marry again, even if everything else in the circumstances is fine. You can’t object, without something to object to (Searle 1975: 348).
A speech act can be abused: you might be in the right circumstances, but your inner state isn’t right, so your speech doesn’t in fact mean what your audience might take it to mean.
if you use one of these formulae when you do not have the requisite thoughts or feelings or intentions then there is an abuse of the procedure, there is insincerity. (Austin 1956: 239)
For example, you may say I promise to feed your cat, knowing full well you have no intention to feed the cat, so you have not sincerely promised; or you may say ‘Congratulations’ while you feel only malice, in which case you have not congratulated.
The characteristically intended consequence of performing a given illocutionary act; e.g., the hearers of an assertion might come to believe not only that the speaker believes \(S\), but they come to share that belief. The hearers of a promise might come to expect its fulfilment.
saying something will often, or even normally, produce certain consequential effects upon the feelings, thoughts, or actions of the audience…: and it may be done with the design, intention, or purpose of producing them… (Austin 1975: 101)
Searle (1975: 344–50) offers a number of classificatory features of illocutionary acts (see also Green 2021: §3.3). Some of the most important include:
Austin has a distinctive view on performatives, claiming that they are not really statements, despite their overt grammar, and ‘are not true or false’ (Austin 1956: 237).
Austin claims that performatives aren’t true or false. Since they seem to be, we need an argument. Here’s one:
On (8): Truth and falsity apply to content; assertion is a kind of force category. So while maybe only assertions commit the speaker to the truth of the utterance (Searle 1975: 354–55); or perhaps truth only matters for assertions (as opposed to pretence); still, the content merely pretended, etc., is true or false.
A broken promise is still a promise; and it’s still a promise even if I formed the intention never to keep in even before making it.
Nevertheless, if you hear me promise, and have no evidence about my wayward intentions, you will assume that I am a cooperative speaker, and assume that I will act as I have promised.
This fits with a theoretical framework we’ve already seen: implicature.
An abuse is then naturally seen as a failure of implicature.
But how can an utterance have an implicature if it is neither true nor false?
Perlocution can help us understand hate speech (Anderson and Barnes 2023).
Other aspects of speech cannot explain why hate speech needs special regulation:
If there is problem caused by hate speech, it is likely to be on the basis of its perlocutionary effects. E.g., in the Australian context, it is
unlawful for a person to do an act, otherwise than in private, if the act is reasonably likely, in all the circumstances, to offend, insult, humiliate or intimidate another person or a group of people; and the act is done because of the race, colour or national or ethnic origin of the other person, or of some or all of the people in the group. (Racial Discrimination Act (Cth) 1975 §18C)
To offend, insult, and intimidate are all perlocutionary acts.
Pornography, as Langton intends to use it, following Catherine MacKinnon, is any representation that depicts people – but in practice, almost always women –
dehumanized as sexual objects, things or commodities; enjoying pain or humiliation or rape; being tied up, cut up, mutilated, bruised, or physically hurt; in postures of sexual submission or servility or display; reduced to body parts, penetrated by objects or animals, or presented in scenarios of degradation, injury, torture; shown as filthy or inferior; bleeding, bruised or hurt in a context which makes these conditions sexual. (Langton 1993: 293–94)
US rulings that pornography is speech, and thus is protected by US constitutional provisions ensuring freedom of speech (Anderson and Barnes 2023: §4), have guided the debate over the harms of pornography.
If hate speech ought to be policed, perhaps other harmful speech – including pornography – ought to be likewise policed.
powerful people can generally do more, say more, and have their speech count for more than can the powerless. If you are powerful, there are more things you can do with your words.
This bears on the question about silence. If you are powerful, you sometimes have the ability to silence the speech of the powerless. One way might be to stop the powerless from speaking at all. Gag them, threaten them, condemn them to solitary confinement. But there is another, less dramatic but equally effective, way. Let them speak. Let them say whatever they like to whomever they like, but stop that speech from counting as an action. More precisely, stop it from counting as the action it was intended to be. … Some speech acts are unspeakable for women in some contexts: although the appropriate words can be uttered, those utterances fail to count as the actions they were intended to be. (Langton 1993: 298–99)
Imagine this: the actor is acting a scene in which there is supposed to be a fire…. It is his role to imitate as persuasively as he can a man who is trying to warn others of a fire. ‘Fire!’ he screams. And perhaps he adds, at the behest of the author, ‘I mean it! Look at the smoke!’ etc. And now a real fire breaks out, and the actor tries vainly to warn the real audience. ‘Fire!’ he screams. ‘I mean it! Look at the smoke!’ etc. (Davidson 1984: 269)
Pornography might … silence refusal, by doing something other than eroticizing refusal itself. It may simply leave no space for the refusal move in its depictions of sex. In pornography of this kind there would be all kinds of locutions the women depicted could use to make the consent move. ‘Yes’ is one such locution. ‘No’ is just another. Here the refusal move is not itself eroticized…: it is absent altogether. Consent is the only thing a woman can do with her words in this game. Someone learning the rules of the game from this kind of pornography might not even recognize an attempted refusal. ‘Coming from her, I took it as consent,’ he might say. Refusal would be made unspeakable for a woman in that context.
If young men can rape without knowing it, then women sometimes fail to secure uptake for their attempted refusals. This is the silence, not simply of frustration, but of disablement. (Langton 1993: 324–25)
identity power is an integral part of the mechanism of testimonial exchange, because of the need for hearers to use social stereotypes as heuristics in their spontaneous assessments of their interlocutor’s credibility. … Notably, if the stereotype embodies a prejudice that works against the speaker, then two things follow: there is an epistemic dysfunction in the exchange – the hearer makes an unduly deflated judgement of the speaker’s credibility, perhaps missing out on knowledge as a result; and the hearer does something ethically bad - the speaker is wrongfully undermined in her capacity as a knower. (Fricker 2007: 16–17)
The speaker sustains such a testimonial injustice iff she receives a credibility deficit owing to identity prejudice [‘prejudice … against people owing to some feature of their social identity’] in the hearer. (Fricker 2007: 28)
Who is the speaker of pornographic speech acts? Do they have the authority and political power to silence and subordinate? Can pornography really be speech: is it an utterance in a context?
Why can’t we say: they are refusals, but they are not acknowledged. Why does the act misfire just because the hearer doesn’t cooperate?
“No” not only means no but is a refusal, however blind to the speaker’s intention the hearer may be. (Bird 2002: 13–14)