The Argument from Evil

God, Faith and Infinity » Lecture 4

Arguments Against the Existence of God

Our Dialectical Position

Alternative Explanations of Apparent Design

(AE1)
The existence of God is not required to explain any of our evidence. (premise)
(AE2)
Extraordinary hypotheses are credible only if they are required in explaining some of our evidence. (Premise)
(AE3)
If the existence of God is an extraordinary hypothesis, it is not credible. (AE1, AE2)
(AE4)
The hypothesis that God exists is an extraordinary one. (Premise)
(AE5)
The existence of God is not credible. (AE3, AE4)
(AEC)
God does not exist (AE5)

What This Argument Doesn’t Show

Logical Arguments from Evil

Arguments from Evil

Two Varieties of Argument from Evil

Mackie’s Argument

(M1)
If God exists, ‘God is wholly good’ (Mackie 1955: 200). (premise)
(M2)
‘a good thing always eliminates evil as far as it can’ (Mackie 1955: 201). (premise)
(M3)
If God exists, God always eliminates evil as far as it can. (M1, M2)
(M4)
If God exists, ‘God is omnipotent’ (Mackie 1955: 200). (premise)
(M5)
‘there are no limits on what an omnipotent thing can do’ (Mackie 1955: 201). (premise)
(M6)
If God exists, God always eliminates all evil. (M3, M4, M5)
(M7)
‘yet evil exists’ (Mackie 1955: 200) – i.e., some evil has not been eliminated. (premise)
(MC)
God does not exist. (modus tollens, M6, M7)

A Persuasive Argument?

What Could a Solution Look Like?

Rejecting M7: There is no Evil

Rejecting M7: Recalibrating Good and Evil

Rejecting M5: No Best World

Rejecting M5: Good Needs Evil

Theodicy Elaborated

Higher Goods Theodicies

Higher Goods

Mill on Higher Pleasures

A Higher Goods Theodicy (Mackie 1955: 206–8)

‘The fatal objection’ (Mackie 1955: 207–8)

Objection to Higher Goods

Free Will Theodicy

Characteristics of Free Will Theodicy

Determination Undermines Freedom: Libertarian Free Will

Libertarianism and Constraints on Actualization

The possibility of exclusively good choices

Another role for free will: afterlife theodicy

Objections to Libertarianism

Objections to the Free Will Theodicy (Tooley 2021: §7.2)

  1. Constraint and coercion isn’t always bad, so it would in fact have been preferable for God to intervene to stop the bad consequences of our evil decisions:

    very few people think that one should not intervene to prevent someone from committing rape or murder. … almost everyone would hold that a failure to prevent heinously evil actions when one can do so would be seriously wrong. (Tooley 2021: §7.2)

  2. I can’t exercise voluntary control over all my bodily movements, but that doesn’t make me unfree. Why couldn’t God have made us free but unable to exercise voluntary control over murdering/torturing/etc. actions?

  3. Many bad outcomes result from natural evils: childhood cancer, or death by tsunami, for example. How can human free will justify the existence of these evils?

Horrendous Evil and Deontological Theodicy

Horrendous Evils

I define ‘horrendous evils’ as ‘evils the participation in (the doing or suffering of) which gives one reason prima facie to doubt whether one’s life could (given their inclusion in it) be a great good to one on the whole’. … horrendous evils seem … to engulf the positive value of a participant’s life. … most people would find in the doing or suffering of them prima facie reason to doubt the positive meaning of their lives. (Adams and Sutherland 2018: 299–300)

The Problem of Horrendous Evils

[Distinguish] between two dimensions of Divine goodness in relation to creation—viz., ‘producer of global goods’ and ‘goodness to’ or ‘love of individual created persons’… we may separate two problems of evil parallel to the two sorts of goodness mentioned ….

… establishing God’s excellence as a producer of global goods does not automatically solve the second problem, especially in a world containing horrendous evils. For God cannot be said to be good or loving to any created persons the positive meaning of whose lives He allows to be engulfed in and/or defeated by evils—that is, individuals within whose lives evils remain undefeated. … [G]lobal and generic approaches … fail to give satisfaction. …

Could the truck driver who accidentally runs over his beloved child find consolation in the idea that this … unintended side-effect was part of the price God accepted for a world with the best balance of moral good over moral evil He could get? (Adams and Sutherland 2018: 302–3)

Deontological and Consequentialist Evils

The Inadequacy of Consequentialist Theodicies

‘Loving Intimacy with God’ (Adams and Sutherland 2018: 309)

Defeatism

Evidential Arguments from Evil

The Quasi-Logical Premises

Rowe’s Crucial Claim

Rowe on Anti-Theodicy

Suppose in some distant forest lightning strikes a dead tree, resulting in a forest fire. In the fire a fawn is trapped, horribly burned, and lies in terrible agony for several days before death relieves its suffering. So far as we can see, the fawn’s intense suffering is pointless. … It must be acknowledged that the case of the fawn’s apparently pointless suffering does not prove that (i) is true.… But it is one thing to know or prove that (i) is true and quite another thing to have rational grounds for believing (i) to be true. …

Is it reasonable to believe that there is some greater good so intimately connected to that suffering that even an omnipotent, omniscient being could not have obtained that good without permitting that suffering or some evil at least as bad? It certainly does not appear reasonable to believe this. … In the light of our experience and knowledge of the variety and scale of human and animal suffering in our world, the idea that none of this suffering could have been prevented by an omnipotent being without thereby losing a greater good or permitting an evil at least as bad seems an extraordinary absurd idea, quite beyond our belief. (Rowe 1979: 337–38)

Theistic Responses

The state of play

The Evil of Divine Judgment

The Problem of Divine Evil

God, if we are to believe an orthodox story, has prescribed eternal torment as a punishment for insubordination. …

along both dimensions, time and intensity, the torment is infinitely worse than all the suffering and sin that will have occurred during the history of life in the universe. … God is supposed to torture the damned forever, and to do so by vastly surpassing all the modes of torment about which we know.

Although those who elaborate the orthodox account are sometimes concerned with the fit between crime and punishment, there is no possibility of a genuine balance. For the punishment of the damned is infinitely disproportionate to their crimes. (Lewis 2007: 232)

A Different Argument

Lewis’ Argument

(L1)
God has damned some people for insubordination.
(L2)
People are insubordinate only if either we are ill-informed about the consequences, or being insubordinate is an unavoidable side-effect of something else valuable (e.g., libertarian free will).
(L3)
If they were ill-informed, then God has damned some people without helping them to avoid it – ‘my eternal prospects were determined by a choice I was forced to make in ignorance’ (Lewis 2007: 235).
(L4)
If they were exercising free will, God has damned some people without helping them to avoid it (e.g., he could have kept free will intact while still doing ‘far more luring and urging than he does’ (Lewis 2007: 234)).
(L5)
God has damned people without helping them to avoid it. (L1–L4, proof by cases)

The Argument, Continued

(L6)
‘[D]amnation is torment’ (Lewis 2007: 233)
(L7)
God has condemned people to eternal torment when he could have helped them to avoid that fate. (L5,L6)
(L8)
God has committed great evil. (L7)

Resisting (L6)

Resisting (L1): Universalism

Christianity, properly so-called, requires a redemption. At its heart is the claim that Jesus was born to save us from something. …

if there’s a redemption, there’ll have to be a distinction between those who take advantage of it and those who don’t. What happens to those who don’t? According to universalism, they are not to be punished. God will place them in some condition without perpetrating divine evil.

The afterlife is a more heterogeneous affair than people have thought. The point of our earthly lives isn’t to divide us into two groups, one to live forever in unimaginable bliss, the other to suffer unimaginable torment. Instead of being tried, we simply discover who we are. …

Not all of us are destined for Christian salvation, for God’s eternal Sabbath, but everyone will receive a well-adapted reward. God does not treat all of us alike. But there is no divine evil. (Lewis 2007: 237–38)

References

Adams, Marilyn McCord and Stewart Sutherland (2018) Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 63: 297–323.
Descartes, René (1641/1996) Meditations on First Philosophy: With Selections from the Objections and Replies, John Cottingham, ed., trans. Cambridge University Press.
Draper, Paul (1989) ‘Pain and Pleasure: An Evidential Problem for Theists’, Noûs 23: 331–50. doi:10.2307/2215486.
Hobart, R E (1934) ‘Free Will as Involving Determination and Inconceivable Without It’, Mind, New Series 43: 1–27. doi:10.1093/mind/XLIII.169.1.
Hume, David (1777/2022) An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Amyas Merivale and Peter Millican, eds. https://davidhume.org/texts/e/.
Leibniz, Gottfried (1710/1985) Theodicy, Austin Farrer, ed.; E M Huggard, trans. Open Court.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm (1686/1989) ‘Discourse on Metaphysics’, in Daniel Garber and Roger Ariew, eds., Philosophical Essays: 35–68. Hackett.
Lewis, David (2007) ‘Divine Evil’, in Louise Antony, ed., Philosophers Without Gods: 231–42. Oxford University Press.
Mackie, J L (1955) ‘Evil and Omnipotence’, Mind 64: 200–212. doi:10.1093/mind/lxiv.254.200.
Mill, John Stuart (1861/1969) Utilitarianism, vol. 10, John M Robson, ed. University of Toronto Press; Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Rowe, William L (1979) The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of Atheism, American Philosophical Quarterly 16: 335–41.
Sober, Elliott (2003) ‘The Design Argument’, in Neil A Manson, ed., God and Design: The Teleological Argument and Modern Science: 25–53. Routledge.
Steward, Helen (2012) A Metaphysics for Freedom. Oxford University Press.
Tooley, Michael (2021) ‘The Problem of Evil’, in Edward N Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/evil/.