Classic philosophical arguments for God’s existence

God, Faith and Infinity » Lecture 2

Arguments for the Existence of God

Scholasticism

Anselm and Aquinas

What is an Argument For the Existence of God?

When is an Argument for God Successful?

Kant’s Taxonomy of Arguments for God

All the paths leading to this goal begin either from determinate experience and the specific constitution of the world of sense as thereby known, and ascend from it, in accordance with laws of causality, to the supreme cause outside the world; or they start from experience which is purely indeterminate, that is, from experience of existence in general; or finally they abstract from all experience, and argue completely a priori, from mere concepts, to the existence of a supreme cause. The first proof is the physico-theological, the second the cosmological, the third the ontological. There are, and there can be, no others. (Kant 1787: A 590/B 618)

The Ontological Argument

Anselm’s Ontological Argument

Lord … we believe You to be something than which nothing greater can be thought. Or is there, then, no such nature [as You], for the Fool has said in his heart that God does not exist? But surely when this very same Fool hears my words “something than which nothing greater can be thought,” he understands what he hears. … So even the Fool is convinced that something than which nothing greater can be thought is at least in his understanding; for when he hears of this [being], he understands [what he hears], and whatever is understood is in the understanding. But surely that than which a greater cannot be thought cannot be only in the understanding. For if it were only in the understanding, it could be thought to exist also in reality – something which is greater. Therefore, if that than which a greater cannot be thought were only in the understanding, then that than which a greater cannot be thought would be that than which a greater can be thought! But surely this [conclusion] is impossible. Hence, without doubt, something than which a greater cannot be thought exists both in the understanding and in reality. (Anselm 1078: 93–94)

The Argument

The Argument, Reconstructed (Oppy and Scott 2010: 74)

(AN1)
The greatest conceivable being (‘that than which a greater cannot be thought’) exists in the understanding. (Premise)
(AN2)
The greatest conceivable being can be conceived to exist in reality. (From AN1)
(AN3)
‘to exist also in reality … is greater [than existing only in the understanding]’ (Premise, Anselm (1078), pp. 93–4)
(AN4)
It is impossible to conceive of a being which is greater than ‘that than which a greater cannot be thought’. (Premise, obvious?)
(ANH)
The greatest conceivable being exists only in the understanding. (Supposition for reductio)
(AN5)
We can conceive of a being which is greater than the greatest conceivable being. (ANH, AN2, AN3)
(ANC)
(Hence) the greatest conceivable being exists not only in the understanding, but also in reality. (AN5, AN4, by reductio of ANH)

Gaunilo’s Perfect Island Parody

Diagnosis?

Worries about AN1

Is Existence a Greatness-Making Quality? (AN3)

Which Being Are We Talking About? (Oppy and Scott 2010: 79)

Existence in the Understanding

Being and Existing

The Cosmological Argument from First Causes

Aquinas’ ‘Second Way’ to God

The second way is based on the notion of an efficient cause:

We find that among sensible things there is an ordering of efficient causes, and yet we do not find – nor is it possible to find – anything that is an efficient cause of its own self. For if something were an efficient cause of itself, then it would be prior to itself – which is impossible.

But it is impossible to go on to infinity among efficient causes. For in every case of ordered efficient causes, the first is a cause of the intermediate and the intermediate is a cause of the last – and this regardless of whether the intermediate is constituted by many causes or by just one. But when a cause is removed, its effect is removed. Therefore, if there were no first among the efficient causes, then neither would there be a last or an intermediate. But if the efficient causes went on to infinity, there would not be a first efficient cause, and so there would not be a last effect or any intermediate efficient causes, either – which is obviously false. Therefore, one must posit some first efficient cause – which everyone calls a God. (Aquinas 1274: 15)

Reconstructing the Argument

(AQ1)
Events form an actual causal chain (‘there is an ordering of efficient causes’).
(AQ2)
Causal chains cannot involve infinitely many causes.
(AQI)
The actual causal chain is finite (it is ‘obviously false’ that it ‘go on to infinity’). (AQ1, AQ2)
(AQ3)
If there are only finitely many causes in a causal chain, and each has a cause, then at least one of them can be found on its own causal chain.
(AQ4)
Nothing can be found on its own causal chain (nothing is ‘prior to itself’).
(AQ5)
A causal chain with finitely many causes has a first cause: something which causes without being caused itself. (AQ3, AQ4)
(AQ6)
The actual causal chain has a first cause. (AQI, AQ5)
(AQ7)
This actual first cause is God.
(AQC)
God exists. (AQ6, AQ7)

Evaluating the Argument: AQ7

Are causes in a chain? Evaluating AQ1

Causal loops – AQ3

No causal loops – AQ4

Infinite Causal Chains AQ2

Identifying God(s)

Another Ontological Argument

The Modal Ontological Argument

  1. It is of the essence of God that He is perfect. (Premise, definition of God from PBT)
  2. It is more perfect to exist necessarily, than to exist contingently. (Premise)
  3. It is of the essence of God that He exists necessarily. (from 1, 2)
  4. It is possible that God exists. (Premise)
  5. It is possible that God exists necessarily. (from 3, 4)
  6. Whatever is possibly necessary is actual. (Premise)
  7. God exists. (from 5, 6)

Evaluating the modal argument: God as a necessary being

Evaluating the modal argument: possible necessity

The Brouwerian intuition

Evaluating the modal argument: the possibility of God

Epistemic possibility and genuine possibility

References

Anselm (1078/2000) Proslogion, Jasper Hopkins and Herbert Richardson, trans. Arthur J Banning Press. http://www.jasper-hopkins.info/proslogion.pdf.
Aquinas (1274/2018) ‘Summa Theologica’. https://www3.nd.edu/~afreddos/summa-translation/Part 1/st1-ques02.pdf.
Arntzenius, Frank and Tim Maudlin (2013) ‘Time Travel and Modern Physics’, in Edward N Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/time-travel-phys/.
Eagle, Antony (2021) Relativity and the A-Theory, in Eleanor Knox and Alastair Wilson, eds., The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Physics: 86–98. Routledge.
Eagle, Antony, PD Magnus, and Tim Button (2022) ‘Forall\(x\) Adelaide’. https://github.com/antonyeagle/forallx-adl/raw/master/forallx-adl.pdf.
Gaunilo (1903) ‘In Behalf of the Fool’, in Sidney Norton Deane, trans., Proslogium; Monologium: An Appendix in Behalf of the Fool by Gaunilo; and Cur Deus Homo. Open Court. https://sourcebooks.fordham.edu/basis/anselm-gaunilo.asp.
Kane, Robert (1984) ‘The Modal Ontological Argument’, Mind 93: 336–50. doi:10.1093/mind/xciii.371.336.
Kant, Immanuel (1787/1933) Critique of Pure Reason, 2nd edition, Norman Kemp Smith, trans. Macmillan.
Oppenheimer, Paul E and Edward N Zalta (1991) ‘On the Logic of the Ontological Argument’, Philosophical Perspectives 5: 509–29. doi:10.2307/2214107.
Oppy, Graham (2021) ‘Ontological Arguments’, in Edward N Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/ontological-arguments/.
Oppy, Graham and Michael Scott, eds. (2010) Reading Philosophy of Religion. Wiley-Blackwell.
Plantinga, Alvin (1974) The Nature of Necessity. Oxford University Press.